Solution Set 13 – Bayesian Games

1. (Exercise) Consider the case that two players have common prior on the space of states of nature, where each state represents the objective value of a commodity. Show that it is impossible that player 1 thinks after any signal he gets that the expected value is strictly above p*whereas player 2 thinks after any signal he gets that the expected value is strictly below p*. Explain why the common prior assumption is crucial for this result.

Let WÌÂ be a finite set of states, p a common prior over W, Ti signals of player i and ti the signal functions with p(ti)>0 for ti ÎTi, i=1,2. If player i thinks after any signal he gets that the expected value is strictly above p*,then åti(w)= ti wcondi(w|ti) >p* for any ti ÎTi. Then the expected value of w w.r.t p is: åwÎW w p(w) = å ti ÎTi p(ti) åti(w)= ti w condi(w|ti) >p*. On the other hand if player j thinks after any signal he gets that the expected value is strictly below p*, then the expected value of w w.r.t p is strictly below p*, a contradiction. The result does not hold without the common prior assumption because in that case, the two expectations of w above are computed w.r.t. different probability measures and need not be the same.

 

2 (Exercise) Construct and prove the one player analogous result of the proposition about the equivalence between the equilibria of the games G1 and G2 described above.

 

Suppose first that s1ÎA1T1 is not a NE of the G1 game. Then there is t1 ÎT1 and a1ÎA1 such that L1(a1,t1)is strictly preferred by (1, t1) to L1(s1(t1),t1), i.e.: åt1(w)= t1 cond1(w|t1) u1(w, a1 )> åt1(w)= t1 cond1(w|t1) u1(w, s1(t1) ). Then defining s1ÎA1T1 by s1’(t1’)= s1 (t1’) for t1¹ t1 and s1’(t1)= s1 (t1) we have: åwÎW p1 (w) u1(w, s1 ’(t1(w)))= å t1’ ÎT1  p1 (t1’)åt1(w)= t1’ cond1(w|t1’) u1(w, s1’(t1’) ) > å t1’ ÎT1  p1 (t1’) åt1(w)= t1’ cond1(w|t1’) u1(w, s1(t1’) )=åwÎW p1 (w) u1(w, s1 (t1(w))), since  p1 (t1)>0. So s1’ is a profitable deviation from s1  in the G2 game, therefore s1  is not a NE of the G2 game.

 

Now let s1ÎA1T1 be a NE of the G1 game, then for any s1ÎA1T1 and t1 ÎT1, L1(s1(t1),t1) is weakly preferred by player 1 to L1(s1’(t1),t1), i.e. åt1(w)= t1 cond1(w|t1) u1(w, s1(t1) ) ³åt1(w)= t1 cond1(w|t1) u1(w,s1’(t1)). Taking the expectation over all t1 ÎT1, we get: åwÎW p1 (w) u1(w, s1 (t1(w)))= å t1ÎT1  p1 (t1)åt1(w)= t1 cond1(w|t1) u1(w, s1(t1) ) ³ å t1ÎT1  p1 (t1) åt1(w)= t1 cond1(w|t1) u1(w, s1’(t1) )=åwÎW p1 (w) u1(w, s1 (t1 (w))). So s1  is also a NE of the G2 game.

3. (More information may hurt)

Consider the Bayesian game in which N = {1, 2}, W = {w1w2}, the set of actions of player 1 is {UD}, the set of actions of player 2 is {LMR}, player 1's signal function is defined by t1(w1) = 1 and t1(w2) = 2, player 2's signal function is defined by t2(w1) = t2(w2) = 0, the belief of each player is (1/2, 1/2), and the preferences of each player are represented by the expected value of the payoff function defined as follows (where 0 < e < 1/2).

State w1:

 

L

M

R

U

1, 2e

1, 0

1, 3e

2, 2

0, 0

0, 3

D

State w2:

 

L

M

R

U

1, 2e

1, 3e

1, 0

2, 2

0, 3

0, 0

D

This game has a unique Nash equilibrium ((D,D), L) (that is, both types of player 1 choose D and player 2 chooses L). The expected payoffs at the equilibrium are (2, 2).

In the game in which player 2, as well as player 1, is informed of the state, the unique Nash equilibrium when the state is w1 is (UR); the unique Nash equilibrium when the state is w2 is (UM). In both cases the payoff is (1, 3e), so that player 2 is worse off than he is when he is ill-informed.

4. (Exchange game)

In the Bayesian game there are two players, say N = {1, 2}, the set of states is W = S × S, the set of actions of each player is {Exchange,Don't exchange}, the signal function of each player i is defined by ti(s1s2) = si, and each player's belief on W is that generated by two independent copies of F . Each player's preferences are represented by the payoff function ui((X, Y), w) = wj if X = Y = Exchange and ui((X, Y), w) = wi otherwise.

Let x be the smallest possible prize and let Mi be the highest type of player i that chooses Exchange. If Mi > x then it is optimal for type x of player j to choose Exchange. Thus if Mi ³ Mj and Mi > x then it is optimal for type Mi of player i to choose Don't exchange, since the expected value of the prizes of the types of player j that choose Exchange is less than Mi. Thus in any possible Nash equilibrium Mi = Mj = x: the only prizes that may be exchanged are the smallest.

5. (Second price auction)Consider a variant of the second-price sealed-bid auction described in the previous lecture in which each player i knows his own valuation vi but is uncertain of the other players' valuations. Suppose that the set of possible valuations is the finite set V and each player believes that every other player's valuation is drawn independently from the same distribution over V. Players maximize their expected  “surplus”.

(a) Model this situation as the Bayesian game .

(b) Show that the game has a BNE where each player bids his valuation. Is it the unique BNE?

(c) Show that bidding is a weakly dominant action for each type of each player to bid his valuation.

 

Please see example 27.1 of Osborne and Rubinstein for part (a). Let us show part (c).  First let ui(b|vi) denote the payoff to player i when the bid profile is b=(bi)iÎNÎÂ+N  and the valuation profile is v=(vi)iÎNÎVN , as in the second price auction game of exercise 2 in problem set 11. We had already shown in that context that it is a weakly dominant action to bid your own valuation, i.e., for any iÎN, b-i =(bj)j¹iÎÂ+N-1  , vi ÎV , and bi ÎÂ+: ui(vi , b-i|vi)³ ui(bi , b-i|vi). Now let a=(a(j, tj))jÎN, tjÎTj be a strategy profile of the associated G1 game, iÎN, vi =ti ÎTi , and and ai ÎAi= Â+. Since ui(ti , (a(j, tj))j¹i |ti)³ ui(ai , (a(j, tj))j¹i |ti) for any t-i=v-iÎVN-1 , we have that åti(w)= ti condi(w|ti) ui(ti , (a(j, tj(w)))j¹i |ti) ³ åti(w)= ti condi(w|ti) ui(ai , (a(j, tj(w)))j¹i |ti). Therefore it is weakly dominant for player (i, ti) to bid his valuation ti =vi . Part (b) follows from part (c). This is not the unique BNE as before, for example the strategy profile where all types of player i always bid above the maximum possible valuation and all types of other players bid 0 is another BNE.