The set of Nash equilibria is the set of profiles b of bids with b1 Î [v2, v1], bj £b1 for all j ¹ 1, and bj = b1 for some j ¹ 1.
It is easy to verify that all these profiles are Nash equilibria. To see that there are no other equilibria, first we argue that there is no equilibrium in which player 1 does not obtain the object. Suppose that player i ¹ 1 submits the highest bid bi and b1 < bi. If bi > v2 then player i's payoff is negative, so that he can increase his payoff by bidding 0. If bi£ v2 then player 1 can deviate to the bid bi and win, increasing his payoff.
Now let the winning bid be b*. We have b* ³v2, otherwise player 2 can change his bid to some value in (v2,b*) and increase his payoff. Also b* £v1, otherwise player 1 can reduce her bid and increase her payoff. Finally, bj = b* for some j ¹ 1 otherwise player 1 can increase her payoff by decreasing her bid.
Comment An assumption in the exercise is that in the event of a tie for the highest bid the winner is the player with the lowest index. If in this event the object is instead allocated to each of the highest bidders with equal probability then the game has no Nash equilibrium.
If ties are broken randomly in this fashion and, in addition, we deviate from the assumptions of the exercise by assuming that there is a finite number of possible bids then if the possible bids are close enough together there is a Nash equilibrium in which player 1's bid is b1Î [v2, v1] and one of the other players' bids is the largest possible bid that is less than b1.
Note also that, in contrast to the situation in the next exercise, no player has a dominant action in the game here.
For any player i the bid bi = vi is a dominant action. To see this, let xi be another action of player i. If maxj¹ibj ³vi then by bidding xi player i either does not obtain the object or receives a nonpositive payoff, while by bidding bi he guarantees himself a payoff of 0. If maxj¹ibj < vi then by bidding vi player i obtains the good at the price maxj¹ibj, while by bidding xi either he wins and pays the same price or loses.
An equilibrium in which player j obtains the good is that in which b1 < vj, bj > v1, and bi = 0 for all players iÏ {1,j}.
where j Î {1,2}\{i}. Let (t1, t2) be a pair of actions. If t1 = t2 then by conceding slightly later than t1 player 1 can obtain the object in its entirety instead of getting just half of it, so this is not an equilibrium. If 0 < t1<t2 then player 1 can increase her payoff to zero by deviating to t1 = 0. Finally, if 0 = t1 < t2 then player 1 can increase her payoff by deviating to a time slightly after t2 unless v1- t2£ 0. Similarly for 0 = t2 < t1 to constitute an equilibrium we need v2 -t1 £ 0. Hence (t1, t2) is a Nash equilibrium if and only if either 0 = t1 < t2 and t2³ v1 or 0 = t2 < t1 and t1 ³v2.
ui(t1,t2) =
-ti if ti < tj vi/2 -ti if ti = tj vi -tj if ti > tj
Comment An interesting feature of this result is that the equilibrium outcome is independent of the players' valuations of the object.
There are n players, each of whose set of actions is OutÈ [0,1]. (Note that the model differs from Hotelling's in that players choose whether or not to become candidates.) Each player prefers an action profile in which he obtains more votes than any other player to one in which he ties for the largest number of votes; he prefers an outcome in which he ties for first place (regardless of the number of candidates with whom he ties) to one in which he stays out of the competition; and he prefers to stay out than to enter and lose.
Let F be the distribution function of the citizens' favorite positions and let m = F -1(1/2) be its median (which is unique, since the density f is everywhere positive).
It is easy to check that for n = 2 the game has a unique Nash equilibrium, in which both players choose m.
The argument that for n = 3 the game has no Nash equilibrium is as follows.
A symmetric finite game that has no symmetric equilibrium is Hawk--Dove (Figure 17.2).
Comment In the next chapter of the book we introduce the notion of a mixed strategy. From the first part of the exercise it follows that a finite symmetric game has a symmetric mixed strategy equilibrium.